Giving Offense: Essays on Censorship

Paperback
from $0.00

Author: J. M. Coetzee

ISBN-10: 0226111768

ISBN-13: 9780226111766

Category: General & Miscellaneous Essays

Winner of the 2003 Nobel Prize in Literature.\ J. M. Coetzee presents a coherent, unorthodox analysis of censorship from the perspective of one who has lived and worked under its shadow. The essays collected here attempt to understand the passion that plays itself out in acts of silencing and censoring. He argues that a destructive dynamic of belligerence and escalation tends to overtake the rivals in any field ruled by censorship.\ From Osip Mandelstam commanded to compose an ode in praise...

Search in google:

Winner of the 2003 Nobel Prize in Literature.J. M. Coetzee presents a coherent, unorthodox analysis of censorship from the perspective of one who has lived and worked under its shadow. The essays collected here attempt to understand the passion that plays itself out in acts of silencing and censoring. He argues that a destructive dynamic of belligerence and escalation tends to overtake the rivals in any field ruled by censorship.From Osip Mandelstam commanded to compose an ode in praise of Stalin, to Breyten Breytenbach writing poems under and for the eyes of his prison guards, to Aleksander Solzhenitsyn engaging in a trial of wits with the organs of the Soviet state, Giving Offense focuses on the ways authors have historically responded to censorship. It also analyzes the arguments of Catharine MacKinnon for the suppression of pornography and traces the operations of the old South African censorship system."The most impressive feature of Coetzee's essays, besides his ear for language, is his coolheadedness. He can dissect repugnant notions and analyze volatile emotions with enviable poise."—Kenneth Baker, San Francisco Chronicle Book Review"Those looking for simple, ringing denunciations of censorship's evils will be disappointed. Coetzee explicitly rejects such noble tritenesses. Instead . . . he pursues censorship's deeper, more fickle meanings and unmeanings."—Kirkus Reviews"These erudite essays form a powerful, bracing criticism of censorship in its many guises."—Publishers Weekly"Giving Offense gets its incisive message across clearly, even when Coetzee is dealing with such murkytheorists as Bakhtin, Lacan, Foucault, and René; Girard. Coetzee has a light, wry sense of humor."—Bill Marx, Hungry Mind Review"An extraordinary collection of essays."—Martha Bayles, New York Times Book Review"A disturbing and illuminating moral expedition."—Richard Eder, Los Angeles Times Book ReviewPublishers WeeklyThe South African writer teases out the implications of cases like Osip Mandelstam's ode to Stalin and Catharine MacKinnon's anti-pornography crusades. (Oct.)

\ Giving Offense\ \ \ \ Essays on Censorship\ \ \ \ By J. M. Coetzee\ \ \ University of Chicago Press\ \ \ \ Copyright © 2003\ \ \ University of Chicago\ All right reserved.\ \ ISBN: 0-226-11176-8\ \ \ \ \ \ Introduction\ \ \ Writing does not flourish under censorship. This does not mean that the\ censor's edict, or the internalized figure of the censor, is the sole or\ even the principal pressure on the writer: there are forms of repression,\ inherited, acquired, or self-imposed, that can be more grievously felt.\ There may even be cases where external censorship challenges the writer in\ interesting ways or spurs creativity. But the Aesopian ruses that\ censorship provokes are usually no more than ingenious; while the\ obstacles that writers are capable of visiting upon themselves are surely\ sufficient in number and variety for them not to invite more.\ Nevertheless, for the common good, for the good of the state, apparatuses\ of regulation and control are from time to time set up, which grow and\ entrench themselves, as is the wont of bureaucracies. It is hard for any\ writer to contemplate the scale of such apparatuses without a disbelieving\ smile. If representations, mere shadows, are indeed so dangerous, one\ reflects, then surely the appropriate countermeasures are other\ representations, counterrepresentations. If mockery corrodes respectfor\ the state, if blasphemy insults God, if pornography demeans the passions,\ surely it will suffice if stronger and more convincing countervoices are\ raised defending the authority of the state, praising God, exalting chaste\ love.\ This response is wholly in accord with the teleology of liberalism, which\ believes in throwing open the marketplace to contending forces because in\ the long run the market tends to the good, that is to say, to progress,\ which liberalism understands in a historical and even metaphysical light.\ It is wholly at odds with the outlook of the more austere branches of\ Islam, Judaism, and Protestant Christianity, which, detecting a seductive\ and devilish force at the root of the power of representation, and thus\ having no reason to expect that, in a war of representations, a war\ without rules, good representations will triumph, prefer to ban graven\ images.\ We have here reached the entry-point into a debate about the rights of the\ individual as against the rights of the collectivity which is familiar\ enough not to need extended rehearsal and to which I have nothing to\ contribute except perhaps a caution against the kind of moral vigilance\ that defines vulnerable classes of people and sets about protecting them\ from harms whose nature they must be kept blind to because (the argument\ goes) merely to know the harm is to suffer it. I refer here primarily to\ children, though the same argument has been made in respect of so-called\ simple believers. We are concerned to protect children, in good part to\ protect them from the consequences of their limitless curiosity about\ sexual matters. But we should not forget that children experience control\ of their explorations-control which by its own premises cannot spell out\ exactly what it is that is forbidden-not as protection but as frustration.\ From the measures adults take to deny the satisfaction of children's\ curiosity, may children not legitimately infer that their curiosity is\ censurable; and from the explanations with which they are provided for\ being constrained-explanations riddled with holes-may they not infer that\ they are not respected as moral agents? May the ethical wrong done to the\ child in the process not be more durable than any harm it may suffer from\ following wherever curiosity leads?\ This is neither an argument for keeping sexually explicit materials away\ from children nor an argument against it. It is a reflection on how harms\ weigh up against each other, on balancing imponderables, choosing between\ evils. In making such choices we might include in our reckoning the\ consideration that to a small child the things that adults do with or to\ each other's bodies are not only intriguing and disturbing but ugly and\ funny too, even silly; the consideration, too, that whether or not the\ child succeeds in blocking the thought that what the people do in the\ picture its parents may do too, it is hard for the parent not to project\ this thought upon the child, and, reexperiencing it through the child, to\ be embarrassed, ashamed, and even angry. Nor should we forget who is most\ embarrassed when to the candid gaze of a child spectacles of gross adult\ nakedness are exposed. The moment is a complex one; but included in our\ desire to keep such sights from the child may there not be a wish not to\ descend, by association, in the child's esteem, not to become the object\ of the child's disgust or amusement? Max Scheler distinguishes between the\ nakedness of an Aphrodite sculpted with such awe that she seems to have a\ veil of modesty about her, and the "deanimation," or loss of soul, that\ occurs when primitive or childish wonder is lost, and the naked body is\ seen with knowing eyes. He links deanimation to what he calls the\ "apperceptive breaking out" of the sexual organs from the body: no longer\ seen as integral with the body, nor yet as "fields of expression of inner\ and passionate movements," the sexual organs-particularly, one might note,\ the male apparatus, with its appearance of extruded viscera-threaten to\ become objects of disgust. It is not strange that we should wish to\ preserve the childhood of children by protecting them from such sights;\ but whose sensibilities are we in the first place guarding, theirs or our\ own?\ The sexual organs, observes Saint Augustine, move independently of the\ will. Sometimes they respond to what we do not want them to respond to;\ sometimes they remain "frozen" when we want to employ them. From this\ disobedience of the flesh, mark of a fallen state, none are exempt, not\ even the guardians of our morals. A censor pronouncing a ban, whether on\ an obscene spectacle or a derisive imitation, is like a man trying to stop\ his penis from standing up. The spectacle is ridiculous, so ridiculous\ that he is soon a victim not only of his unruly member but of pointing\ fingers, laughing voices. That is why the institution of censorship has to\ surround itself with secondary bans on the infringement of its dignity.\ From being sour to being laughed at for being sour to banning laughter at\ what is sour is an all-too-familiar progression in tyranny, one that\ should give us further cause for caution.\ In the above similitude, I need hardly point out that the one who\ pronounces the ban does not have to be male. The one who pronounces the\ ban by that act lays claim to the phallus, but the phallus in its mundane\ form as penis. Taking up the position of censor, this one becomes, in\ effect, the blind one, the one at the center of the ring in the game of\ blind man's buff. For a time, until the blindfold that at the same time\ marks him, elevates him, and disables him can be passed on, it is his fate\ to be the fool who stumbles about, laughed at and evaded. If the spirit of\ the game, the spirit of the child, is to reign, the censor must accept the\ clownship that goes with blind kingship. The censor who refuses to be a\ clown, who tears off the blindfold and accuses and punishes the laughers,\ is not playing the game. He thereby becomes, in Erasmus's paradox, the\ true fool, or rather, the false fool. He is a fool because he does not\ know himself a fool, because he thinks that, being in the center of the\ ring, he is king.\ Children are not, qua children, innocent. We have all been children and\ know-unless we prefer to forget-how little innocent we were, what\ determined efforts of indoctrination it took to make us into innocents,\ how often we tried to escape from the staging-camp of childhood and how\ implacably we were herded back. Nor do we inherently possess dignity. We\ are certainly born without dignity, and we spend enough time by ourselves,\ hidden from the eyes of others, doing the things that we do when we are by\ ourselves, to know how little of it we can honestly lay claim to. We also\ see enough of animals concerned for their dignity (cats, for instance) to\ know how comical pretensions to dignity can be.\ Innocence is a state in which we try to maintain our children; dignity is\ a state we claim for ourselves. Affronts to the innocence of our children\ or to the dignity of our persons are attacks not upon our essential being\ but upon constructs-constructs by which we live, but constructs\ nevertheless. This is not to say that affronts to innocence or dignity are\ not real affronts, or that the outrage with which we respond to them is\ not real, in the sense of not being sincerely felt. The infringements are\ real; what is infringed, however, is not our essence but a foundational\ fiction to which we more or less wholeheartedly subscribe, a fiction that\ may well be indispensable for a just society, namely, that human beings\ have a dignity that sets them apart from animals and consequently protects\ them from being treated like animals. (It is even possible that we may\ look forward to a day when animals will have their own dignity ascribed to\ them, and the ban will be reformulated as a ban on treating a living\ creature like a thing.)\ The fiction of dignity helps to define humanity and the status of humanity\ helps to define human rights. There is thus a real sense in which an\ affront to our dignity strikes at our rights. Yet when, outraged at such\ affront, we stand on our rights and demand redress, we would do well to\ remember how insubstantial the dignity is on which those rights are based.\ Forgetting where our dignity comes from, we may fall into a posture as\ comical as that of the irate censor.\ Life, says Erasmus's Folly, is theater: we each have lines to say and a\ part to play. One kind of actor, recognizing that he is in a play, will go\ on playing nevertheless; another kind of actor, shocked to find he is\ participating in an illusion, will try to step off the stage and out of\ the play. The second actor is mistaken. For there is nothing outside the\ theater, no alternative life one can join instead. The show is, so to\ speak, the only show in town. All one can do is to go on playing one's\ part, though perhaps with a new awareness, a comic awareness.\ We thus arrive at a pair of Erasmian paradoxes. A dignity worthy of\ respect is a dignity without dignity (which is quite different from\ unconscious or unaffected dignity); an innocence worthy of respect is an\ innocence without innocence. As for respect itself, it is tempting to\ suggest that this is a superfluous concept, though for the workings of the\ theater of life it may turn out to be indispensable. True respect is a\ variety of love and may be subsumed under love; to respect someone means,\ inter alia, to forgive that person an innocence that, outside the theater,\ would be false, a dignity that would be risible.\ (Continues...)\ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ \ Excerpted from Giving Offense\ by J. M. Coetzee\ Copyright © 2003\ by University of Chicago.\ Excerpted by permission.\ All rights reserved. No part of this excerpt may be reproduced or reprinted without permission in writing from the publisher.\ Excerpts are provided by Dial-A-Book Inc. solely for the personal use of visitors to this web site.\ \

Preface and Acknowledgments1Taking Offense12Emerging from Censorship343Lady Chatterley's Lover: The Taint of the Pornographic484The Harms of Pornography: Catharine MacKinnon615Erasmus: Madness and Rivalry836Osip Mandelstam and the Stalin Ode1047Censorship and Polemic: Solzhenitsyn1178Zbigniew Herbert and the Figure of the Censor1479Apartheid Thinking16310The Work of the Censor: Censorship in South Africa18511The Politics of Dissent: Andre Brink20412Breyten Breytenbach and the Reader in the Mirror215Notes233Works Cited269Index285

\ Publishers Weekly - Publisher's Weekly\ The South African writer teases out the implications of cases like Osip Mandelstam's ode to Stalin and Catharine MacKinnon's anti-pornography crusades. (Oct.)\ \ \ \ \ Library JournalSouth African writer Coetzee (Master of Petersburg, LJ 9/1/94) promises a compelling collection of essays of the nature of political censorship in literature. However, this book falls short of that promise, delivering instead an overly erudite and dense dissection of the major works of frequently censored literature. To his credit, the collection of works Coetzee has amassed is impressive-from Lady Chatterly's Lover to Catherine MacKinnon's antipornography treatises, for example. His essay "Apartheid Thinking" is an important summary of a particularly painful chapter in the history of political censorship. Yet there is little here a general reader would find fresh or interesting. For larger academic collections.-Diane G. Premo, SILS, SUNY at Buffalo\ \ \ Hazel RochmanRefusing to see the writer under censorship as either a moral giant or a helpless innocent, the great South African novelist Coetzee relates the experience of Afrikaans writers under apartheid to that of writers under the Soviet state. In both regimes, the ratio of censors to writers was about 10 to 1. Coetzee's prizewinning novels, such as "Waiting for the Barbarians" (1980), are spare and elliptical. Here, however, he writes in his academic mode (he's professor at the University of Cape Town), and these essays clunk with jargon about "intertexed constellations of signifiers." He's always qualifying minutiae in parentheses. In fact, the most moving essay here confronts why he writes in that convoluted way, "overreading and overwriting" : the censor intrudes on your thinking, always there, repudiated, but always there. From his personal experience, Coetzee recognizes his "paranoia" in censored writers everywhere, from Breyten Breytenbach in prison under the scrutiny of his apartheid jailers, to Osip Mandelstam ordered to compose an ode to Stalin. The censor becomes a secret and shameful intimate.\ \ \ \ \ Kirkus ReviewsThese closely argued essays on censorship's insidious subtleties make for dense but rewarding reading.\ As a noted South African writer under apartheid, Coetzee (The Master of Petersburg, 1994, etc.) long suffered the stifling shadow of the censor. Indeed, almost half of the essays in this collection concern South Africa's particular brand of censorship and how it was leveled at fellow writers such as André Brink and Breyten Breytenbach. Broadening his examination, Coetzee also looks at Solzhenitsyn's struggles with the Soviet state, undercuts Catherine MacKinnon's dogmatic anti-pornography stance, deconstructs D.H. Lawrence's belief in breaking taboos, and closely reads the works of several writers operating under censorship conditions. Those looking for simple, ringing denunciations of censorship's evils will be disappointed. Coetzee explicitly rejects such noble tritenesses. Instead, drawing on the works of modern theorists such as Lacan, Foucault, and Girard, he pursues censorship's deeper, more fickle meanings and unmeanings. In his essay on the South African Publications Appeal Board, for example, he reveals the unreasoning paranoia that governs even the most "enlightened" censorship. In other words, censorship can never be a wholly rational act. Almost every page is thick with such provocative insights and ideas, but Coetzee does not always do his arguments justice. Unlike his lucid, elegant fictions, here he is often unnecessarily opaque and obscure. He has the South African intellectual's fatal fondness for academic jargon (though not the usual accompanying cant), and his logic occasionally short- circuits.\ But his erudition and intelligence remain truly formidable throughout. And as Coetzee's own experience has shown, censorship ultimately fights a losing battle: "The artist, if he is patient enough and persistent enough, always wins, or at least emerges on the winning side."\ \ \